Populo Volume 2 Issue 1

McMahan (2005), which could arguably lead into eugenics despite Brecher’s (2011)

arguments.

As touched upon above, what we need to know about such prevention of genetic

conditions, is why they are so much more controversial than arguing for preventing

non-genetic conditions. Brecher (2011) acknowledges that one such difference is that

when talking about genetic conditions, it is the intrinsic link to identity claimed by

disabled people that morally differentiates the two- he, for example, points to the fight

by the deaf community to protect the right to bring deaf children into the world as a

way of asserting deafness as an important identity. Brecher (2011), however, does not

consider this a convincing argument, nor does he consider the social model of

disability entirely convincing as rebukes to preventing disabled births, as he concludes

that if a disability cannot be changed by adapting social norms to accommodate that

disability, then it devalues no one to eliminate said disability.

Bostom and Savulescu (2009) similarly suggest that arguing against enhancement

for the reason it would send the message that those who are unenhanced are

intrinsically worth less, in this essay’s case, those who are allowed to be born disabled,

is distinct from the message that some properties are not as good as other properties

for people to have, again in this discussion’s case, that the property of being disabled

is not as good to have as the property of being abled. Bostom and Savulescu (2009),

similarly to Brecher (2011), argue that this latter message is not immoral to send if it is

true. Thus, genetic enhancement is not an immoral practice to encourage. Thus, if it is

not an immoral practice, is it the moral option? Does this then insinuate that parents

who do not enhance their children are not making the moral choice and are morally

blameworthy should they refuse to enhance their children ‘against’ disability

22

Made with FlippingBook HTML5