Populo Volume 2 Issue 2

(1859) ‘Harm Principle’ was notable: “ Power can [only] be rightfully

exercised... to prevent harm to others ” (p.18). His attitude towards epistemic

freedom reinforces this, as a vehement defender of speech’s instrumental value,

professing there should be the “ liberty of... discussing... any doctrine ” even if

“ immoral ” (unpopular) (p.22). While Rawls justified free speech as enabling

justice, for Mill free speech permits falsities to be rectified through “ discussion ”

(p.35), or, for partial correctness, enables truth to emerge (p.8). Mill asserts

denying opinions is assuming “ infallibility ” (p.30). While he attests there is “ no

absolute certainty ” (p.33), in relative correctness, he argues, without discussion,

an opinion’s “ grounds ” are forgotten (p.66), becoming a “ dead dogma ” (p.59).

Truth, by Mill, maximises happiness, contributing to his utilitarian stance

(p.20).

Regarding contemporary speech, Mill’s arguments make likely his defence of

one’s right to express oneself as one pleases, even if in-factual or offensive,

positing no speech regulation. Offending (through hateful/false rhetoric), in

Mill’s opinion, is not ‘harm’ (p.142), therefore the ‘Harm Principle’ does not

apply. Nevertheless, Mill recognises potential implications. He analogises

offensive speech’s potential to harm in certain contexts, for example, spouting

hateful corn-dealer rhetoric “ to a... mob... before the house of a corn-dealer ”

(p.94). In a suberogatory sense, while he believes all speech deserves

protection, there are circumstances where potential incitement to harm, or even

customary morality, should prevail. In my preceding examples, Mill would

likely support Muhammad Adil’s COVID-19 denial, to give “ all sides of the

truth ” (p.81). Similarly, Mill would challenge Luton’s homophobia fine, unless,

perhaps, such chants were sung before a mob.

8

Made with FlippingBook HTML5