Marist Undergraduate Philosophy Journal Vol VI 2023

Diotima: The Marist Undergraduate Philosophy Journal

contrast, if regret was concerned with the outcome sense of mistake, it would, as

Jacobson puts it, “ [T]hreaten the idea that regret serves as a sentiment whose

function involves learning from one’s mistakes, because cases of loss without error

should not motivate any change of policy. ” 7

I will instead defend the outcome sense of mistake. I will argue that agent-

regret is fitting only in cases where the decision produces a bad outcome. As such,

regret is not connected with motivating a policy change. Rather, I will argue that

what motivates a policy change is a distinct but related emotion to regret, what I

will call ‘ self-reproach. ’

The distinction between these two senses of mistake interestingly parallels

a central debate in ethics; namely, between deontology and consequentialism.

Recall that for consequentialism, only the consequences or outcomes of the action

matter morally speaking. What Thomas Nagel calls the causal pathways – that is,

how the action was brought about are totally irrelevant. 8 Deontologists also value

the consequences of actions, but they are mainly concerned with whether the

action was brought about in the right kind of way: for instance, that it did not

involve a wrongful violation of rights or other norms. 9

In what follows, I argue that regret is best understood as a consequentialist

emotion. To clarify, I am not making a claim in normative ethics. Rather, I am

making a claim about moral psychology. I will argue that regret resembles

consequentialism as far as it is only concerned with outcomes, which is naturally

related to the outcome sense of mistake. Similarly, I argue that self-reproach is a

deontological emotion insofar as it is primarily concerned with causal pathways,

which is instead naturally related to the deliberation sense of mistake. I will give a

7 D’Arms and Jacobson, 119. 8 Th omas Nagel, “War and Massacre,” in Mortal Questions , (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,1979), 54. 9 As John Rawls, a famous deontologist, writes in A Theory of Justice: “All ethical doctrines worth our attention take consequences into account in judging rightness. One which did not would be simply irrational, crazy,” 30.

Volume VI (2023)

41

Made with FlippingBook Annual report maker