Marist Undergraduate Philosophy Journal Vol VI 2023

Agent-Regret and Regret Consequentialism

full account of the main differences between regret and self-reproach in section 4.

To approach this debate systematically, I will consider four types of cases that

exhaust logical space: (1) good deliberation/good outcome; (2) bad deliberation/good

outcome; (3) good deliberation/bad outcome; (4) bad deliberation/bad outcome. I

aim to identify what is essential to regret. By ‘essential’, I mean: What are the

necessary and sufficient conditions for regret to be fitting? The cases can be

represented as follows.

Is Regret Fitting?

Good Outcome

Bad Outcome

Good Deliberation

?

?

Bad Deliberation

?

?

I will argue that each case is either neutral (Case 1) or best interpreted as

supporting regret consequentialism over regret deontology (Cases 2-4).

Case 1: Good Deliberation/ Good Outcome

Rock/Paper/Scissors : Someone challenges you to a game of

rock/paper/scissors. If you win, you get $10. If they win, you lose nothing.

You accept and win, netting yourself $10.

Imagine you regret your decision to play. Is your regret fitting? Clearly not, but

why? Regret deontologists will argue that regret is unfitting because you made no

deliberative error. You chose the highest expected value among the available

options, so you made the best decision. Thus, your regret is unfitting. By contrast,

regret consequentialists will argue that regret is unfitting since you won $10. Your

decision had the highest actual value of all the available options, meaning it

resulted in the best outcome. Both regret deontologists and regret

consequentialists agree with the commonsense intuition that regret is unfitting

Volume VI (2023)

42

Made with FlippingBook Annual report maker